Tuesday 18 June 2013

Foresight



Foresight - Meinrad Calleja

INTRODUCTION

One of the distinguishing features of modernity was an assumption to be able to precisely make certain predictions. The assumed efficacy of these predictions was based on accurate empirical measurements of contextual/ ecological features, the conjoining of various ‘scientific’ interpretative disciplines, and the assumed causal relationships and potential correspondences between the findings. Such ‘tested’ empiricism was the basis of what is known as ‘forecast’ laws.

While ‘forecast’ is thus concerned with predictions, ‘foresight’ is primarily about anticipating uncertainty. It involves dealing with ambiguity. Foresight looks at the obstacles of ‘forecast’ scenarios and seeks to provide contingency for their eventual elimination. While ‘forecast’ deals with ‘determinism’, ‘foresight’ deals with a/in/un- determined scenarios. In this respect, certain mundane applications in financial markets (e.g. futures, bonds, securities), trade (e.g. insurance, commodity provisions), commerce (e.g. market analysis, advertising), security (e.g. Echeleon, intelligence gathering), and industry (e.g. product design, technology) seem to rely on forecast provisions, some of which seem to infer seminal premises abstracted from foresight. Applications like silicon and nanotechnology are examples.   

Foresight deals with intentional actions that are not necessarily subject to empirical verification, causal laws, or rational deliberation. Foresight is thus a participatory intuitive reasoning process. Foresight is concerned with direction setting, determining priorities, anticipatory intelligence, consensus generation, and advocacy. It is based on the development, fusion, and cross-hybridization of technologies, consultation, scenario creation (‘steep’), patent analysis, critical technologies, and technological road-mapping. It focuses on hybrid approaches to innovation in market and industrial research and development while seeking to engage stakeholders. It is both a commercial as well as an educational tool. It may be applied for social demographic planning. It is crucial to any knowledge-based deliberation process.

A concrete application of ‘foresight’ would be ‘intelligent-foresight’ – a form of video monitoring that can scan anomaly detection to check trend-spotting comparatively to alert specific anomalies. Data warehouses use holography and quantum computers, with enhanced quantum cryptography, activating IT-denominated ‘foresight’. Hind-casting algorithms are used to make foresight scenarios. These often include cluster analysis of diverse, even unrelated, individual molecular components. Such applications have been used in meteorology and security intelligence. The development of telematics or telephony business and IT denominated applications seem to have been tangibly directed by foresight imperatives. Perhaps GM agricultural production and its capacity for cross hybridization and polynisation may to a certain extent be termed symmetrical with foresight derivatives. How do we demarcate our perimeter between forecast and foresight?

This paper will discuss some fundamental issues concerning foresight and the implications that orbit around its application and limitations. To assume foresight is a supplement of forecast is quite inadequate and any attempt to focus on foresight in this light actually defies the objective. Theoretically, one ought to factor in the limitations and obstacles that forecast either ignores outright or seeks to unsatisfactorily address through insufficient determination. In this paper we shall explore some of the theoretical underpinnings of foresight philosophy.           

EPISTEMOLOGY MATRIX

Foresight critically addresses two important features of ‘forecast’ - ‘professional impairment’ and ‘hyper-scientization’. ‘Hyper-scientization’ are ‘those approaches that stress intellectual elegance and consistency to the seemingly permissible neglect of ‘reality’.’[1] Reality includes ambiguity and uncertainty. Lindblom’s ‘professional impairment’ is ‘the imposition of an alien perspective, disregard for the knowledge of the observed, over concern with rigour, operationalisation and coherence at the expense of insight into the context of action and into the meaning with which actors endow situations.’[2] Foresight privileges ‘context-insight’ and ‘meaning-endowment’ while to a certain extent de-sacralizing rigidly configurated knowledge.

Foresight is an emancipatory approach that probes virgin configurations of knowledge by broadening boundaries, inverting cluster components, and redefining domains. Foresight is orientated to de-formulate ideality and ideal goals. System dynamics are dismantled and rearranged according to untested exploratory modelling. Scanning scenario planning to generate ideas may involve the engagement of hitherto uninitiated participants. Foresight enfranchises an a-credentialist perspective to transcend ‘specialization’.   

Foresight thus also deals with knowledge analysis. Foucault has shown that ‘the possibility of a science of empirical orders requires an analysis of knowledge – an analysis that must show how the hidden (and as it were confirmed) continuity of being can be reconstituted by means of the temporal connection provided by discontinuous representations.’[3] Foresight deals with this ‘discontinuity’. In this context we may already state that foresight is crucial to steering epistemology by directing knowledge to move from a mere configuration of tested reliability to a more hybrid approach. 

Every truth-shift, even mere paradigm shifts, are based on the constituent truth status of the knowledge-matrix, even when such an undertaking revealed the errors in the former, as Kuhn has shown us in theoretically mapping out all major scientific breakthroughs. Knowledge, taken as a ‘taxonomy of truths’, is based on this consistency and continuity, and ‘plausibility’. Occasionally errors are revealed; sometimes they are only superseded by new errors. Kuhn insists that scientific change occurs by ‘revolutions’ that make former assumed verities redundant. When a given scientific matrix is assumed to be ‘true’ it is a ‘paradigm’. Can we determine these errors? Sometimes, not even in retrospect. However, ‘foresight’ is concerned with tentatively addressing this ambiguity. It may contribute to innovatively and creatively designing qua knowledge.

In a scenario of accelerated technological change one may be inclined to attach a transitory and ephemeral value to technological innovation. While innovation management is concerned with endowing end-users with skills to access technological applications and the ethos they require to adapt to rapid change, foresight scans the environment to detect anomalies that could potentially create disruptive lacunae and rationality deficits to restore planning coherence and stability for the future. However, this is not to say that foresight may be reduced to a tool of transition that seeks to make a compensatory deposit to settle change or bridge irreconcilable paths. Foresight ought to settle ambivalence by disrupting neat boundaries and sedimentation to expose the despotism of rational order.   

Foucault has pointed out, ‘if one wishes to undertake an archaeological analysis of knowledge itself [...] one must reconstitute the general system of thought whose network, in its posivity, renders an interplay of simultaneous and apparently contradictory opinions possible. It is this network that defines the conditions that make a controversy or problem possible, and that bears the historicity of knowledge.’[4] Foresight attempts to focus on these ‘posivity networks’ to jettison unnecessary stages, supersede sterile conceptions, and transcend obstacles. Such a task requires the abolition of all mechanistic schema and template diagrams.   

Each conception of knowledge seeks to create a body of knowledge that it defines as ‘objective’ and ‘scientific’, or, to put it bluntly, ‘true’ and ‘correct’. These discourses attempt to establish an assumed unity of relations, or as Foucault calls it, a ‘discursive constellation’.[5] Foresight assumes dealing with unpredictable clusters of uncertainty by anticipating them and eliminating unnecessary consumption of resources. 

EMPIRICISM

When we examine the rationality governing empirically formatted ‘forecast’ we note that there was an attempt to: (a) selectively isolate a number of variables, (b) assume correspondences between them, (c) draw teleological aggregates from a ‘discursive constellation’, (d) arrive at ‘axiomatic’ symbols, and (e) confer universally valid truth status on formulae that help maintain this scientific/ professional body of knowledge and their interpretations. This is done through the conjunction of ‘taxinomonia’ and ‘genesis’. [Sociological] predictions based on empiricism always represented the climax of these relations through verification and confirmation. Foresight deals with disruption of order scenarios. Using an analogy Popper makes, we may postulate that forecast deals with ‘clockwork’, while foresight deals with ‘clouds’. Our physical laws have shown reality is often a cloud reality. Newtonian science has allowed peeking holes to alert us to these facts, many of which were rather naively relegated to the periphery of inquiry as though they were mere exceptions that enforce the rule, rather than demolish it.  

Ambiguity and uncertainty are essential features of our ontological primacy. Life, indeed human life, cannot be reduced to simplistic signs, certainly not coefficient signs. Modern forecast empiricism seems to consider the body of knowledge it assumes is its speciality or its exclusive sphere of influence is subject to established applications and correspondences borrowed from other areas. Often this is based on an over-determination of ‘science’.

MATEMATISATION

Canguilhem cites Koyre who stated bluntly that science is theory, while theory is fundamentally mathematization. (‘La science est theorie et que la theorie est fondamentalement mathematisation.’[6]) Canguilhem was critical of this over-determination. That is why we are with Foucault when he states ‘all hasty mathematization or naive formalisation of the empirical seems like ‘pre-critical’ dogmatism and a return to the platitudes of Ideology.’[7] Mathematics has become the proto-language of all science. Foresight addresses this deficit by acknowledging contradictions and either adapting to them or eliminating the contradictions outright.

Sometimes, mathematization ‘laws’ are shaped both a posterior and a priori. These laws may actually be totally random and they may even defy certain rationality or logic. If one were to toss a coin, for example, one would expect both sides to appear as equal, which is rarely the case. The Monte Carlo fallacy, for example, is based on the anticipation of equal tosses for ‘heads’ and ‘tails’ to the extent that when one side of the coin appears more frequently than another, one is inclined to imminently expect the other side to start compensating the deficit. This forecasting is fallacious. Reality need not adhere to plausible ‘forecasts’. We cannot even ‘hindcast’ correctly. Doctrines of ‘forecasting’ applied to policy design are often unwittingly based on these calculations. However, we can also assemble arbitrary ‘laws’ and ‘forms’ based solely on a notion of ‘experience’ which would make our errors or prejudices less obvious. Pathologies are based on such empirical schematisation. This accentuates the importance of ‘foresight’.

Most of the sciences of sociology are corroborated by empiricism that is based on mathematization stretched to its limits, often assembled through a methodology akin to the Monte Carlo Fallacy. Criminology, for example, was actually a branch of the ‘sociology of deviance’, but gained its independence as an autonomous subject resembling a science when it extended its mathematization, and conjoined other sciences like, for example, biology. ‘Mathematization’ is never neutral or innocent.

Karl Popper, in his ‘Conjectures and Refutations – The Growth of Scientific Knowledge’, refers to the empiricism of ‘astrology’ to explain how conjecture can not only claim to be ‘scientific empiricism’ but also appear ‘plausible’ and ‘rational’. Forecast technologies are often based entirely on a sort of so called ‘astrologically-interpreted empiricism’[8] as though we were accepting the language of ‘horoscopes’ as ‘scientific’. This analogy to ‘astrology’ shows us that even reliably collated and rigorously corroborated observations, - that are empirical facts - as occur in the case of ‘astronomy’, can be selectively ‘interpreted’ subjectively. These are simply ‘modes of rationality’ or ‘languages’ based on pure conjecture. What Russell refers to as ‘logical fictions’.[9]

Roseanne Benn discusses the contemporary ideological role of ‘mathematics’ in the light of recurring ambiguity and uncertainty. ‘The relationship between mathematics and reality became increasingly problematic and puzzling [...] Attempts to either picture the world as it is or use a perfectly consistent neutral meta-language ultimately failed. Indeed, in late modernity, mathematics appears to deliberately deceive by masking even awareness of the absence of any reality. Within the wider context of human thought and experience, the development of mathematics can bee seen as the ‘grand narrative’ of academic Western mathematics which pathologises inability to relate to this mathematics and ignores or marginalises alternative or ‘other’ mathematics. Difference is repressed, the central narrative is held as certain and the workings of power are concealed.

This characterisation of mathematics has provided an elaborate rationale and legitimisation for the pre-eminence of academic Western mathematics and has contributed to the dominance of certain cultural groups in society. The mathematical narratives of subordinate groups have been denigrated or ignored. [...]. To question the certainty of mathematics is to challenge the hegemony, irreversibility and sweeping narrative of modernity.’[10] The philosophy of foresight is concerned with questioning and challenging these assumed verities and illusory synergy. Foresight is used in complexity research that engages non-linear component parts to explore unpredictability and inexplicability not otherwise ascertainable.  

We know from Russell that ‘the mathematicians have constructed a multiplicity of possible spaces, and have shown that many logical schemes would fit the empirical facts. Logic shows that space is not ‘the subject matter of geometry’, since an infinite number of subject matters satisfy any given kind of geometry. Psychology disentangles the contributions of various senses to the construction of space, and reveals the all-embracing space of physics as the outcome of many empirically familiar correlations.’[11] This irrationality is addressed by ‘foresight’.

Wittgenstein made it amply clear that ‘the propositions of mathematics are equations, and therefore pseudo-propositions.’[12] Foresight seeks to reveal the subjective, arbitrary, and ephemeral nature of these pseudo-sciences, and their misuse in forecast-related discourses. Certainty is not just questioned rhetorically, but it is actually translated as uncertainty and ambiguity, and tentatively steered to become an opportunity. Foresight illustrates alternative ‘language games’. Rather than alternative ‘rules’ we may need to consider their abolishment. 

On the question of ‘arbitrariness’ we can draw on Adorno who stated ‘the irrationality, in which the philosophically absolutized ratio perishes, confesses to the arbitrariness of whatever seeks to eliminate the arbitrary.’[13] However, we are not negating the arbitrary to privilege those interpretations that are not arbitrary; rather we are merely accentuating this arbitrariness. Adorno agrees that ‘mathematics is tautology also by the limitation of its total dominance to what itself has already prepared and formed.’[14] Here ‘foresight’ is elucidating this ‘total dominance’ as a ‘limitation’ that is rigidly and mechanistically enforced in the hope that these ‘forms’ and ‘laws’ may be transcended. 

DIALECTICAL APPROACH

Today we emphasise an assumed ideal rationality that emphatically claims objective valence – hence ‘responsibility’- which is foisted as ‘scientific’. In the area of establishing how ‘uncertainties’ occur, with the ontological implications related to existential responsibility and free-will, the governing rationality claims to have achieved an acknowledged degree of reliability and rigour, particularly after the alleged breakthroughs of assumed unquestioned ‘certainty’ in DNA, genetics, bio-technology, ITT control, satellite tracking and surveillance, quantum computers, cybernetics, nanotechnology and forensic science. In the field of understanding ‘why’ ambiguity occurred one may be tempted to assume sociology, social anthropology, neuro-biology, psychiatry, psychology, phenomenology, and hermeneutics have tendered plausible readings. However, this has not settled issues of ambiguity or eliminated uncertainty. Plausibility is in fact in some cases an obstacle. 

Bachelard states that ‘phenomenology does not involve an empirical description of phenomena. Empirical description involves enslavement to the object by decreeing passivity on part of the subject.’[15] Foresight ought to address both the issue of ‘passivity’ of the subject and ‘enslavement’ to the object. The crucial error is often dogmatic ‘methodology’. Bachelard refers to ‘epistemological obstacles’ and ‘epistemological breaks’ in this light.

As Gadamer puts it, ‘every event of understanding […] is essentially dialectical.’[16] If we ignore this dialect, we can only reach forlorn conclusions. ‘All modern sciences possess a deeply rooted alienation that they impose on the natural consciousness and of which we need to be aware. This alienation already reached reflective awareness in the very beginning stages of modern science in the concept of method.’[17] We have to avoid what Gadamer refers to as ‘methodological sterility’,[18] (which is not to be confused with Searle’s ‘referential opacity’). This is one of the crucial aspects of foresight. Foresight ought to transcend this sterility and address it.

DESPOTIC CYBERNETICS

Cybernetics, coined by Norbert Wiener in 1947, refers to systems of communication that manipulate information by feedback and feedforward to enhance the concept of control by taking account of these fluctuations.[19] Karl Deutsch’s ‘cybernetic-reasoning’ uses the concept of [‘negative’ or ‘positive’] ‘feedback’ (entropy of ‘input’) as a measurement of communication. ‘The difference between the entropy of the input and the equivocation of the input with respect to the output thus measures the capacity of the channel as a reliable conveyor of information.’[20] Our over-determination of empiricism is based on this modeling.

In his ‘Cybernetics and the Philosophy of Mind’, Sayre quotes Tribus that ‘entropy only measures the extent of our ignorance about the detailed behaviour of a system’.[21] These initial obstacles sought to enhance empiricism by diverse fonts of induction, and prognostic and agnostic deliberations that included a reconfiguration of both subject and object depiction. Econometrics, simulation and modeling were reformatted. We may be entitled to assume this is being done to preserve the system’s ‘homeostatically’ protected parameter. This ensures the system has ‘recovery’ powers or capacity. A ‘homeostatic’ system of this sort maintains its structure through constant piecemeal change and incremental improvements. In short, parameters can be changed.

Here we are experiencing a type of system ‘of feedback that works to maintain the organism in a certain relationship with its operating environment, rather than to sustain a certain internal state. […] ‘Heterotelic feedback’ which ‘differs from ‘homeostasis’ in directing the response of the environmentally stimulated system back to the environment rather than containing it within the system itself.’[22] New contemporary modes of foresight rationality, that are also modes of domination, are based on rendering these systems more controllable and predictable. Systems of ‘foresight’ used in contemporary policy-making ensure these forms of influence are always more efficient in not only controlling the derivative context and predicting the future, but actually designing and directing it to deal with uncertainty. This can only be done through innovation management and codification that engineers this social process politically and culturally through holistic dissemination policies.

While it is true ‘cybernetics’ is a ‘machine-based’ form of methodology and not a ‘human’ application, its form of rationality does permeate human reasoning. A machine does not desire and is thus an expression of ‘absolute repression’ because it has been programmed a priori to exclude all human reasoning. It cannot experience ‘ressentiment’. But where does this leave ontology?

ONTOLOGICAL IMPICATIONS OF SOCIAL ENGINEERING

Foresight also deals with ethical and moral ramifications. Many doctrines of radical social engineering (for example, genetic engineering, or eugenics) are influenced by, or, perhaps, merely symmetrical with, cybernetic reasoning applications or their cloned subsidiary derivatives. Discourses in circulation seem to gradually influence these doctrines. Note how genetically modified agricultural produce and human genetic cloning are gradually gaining plausibility. They infiltrate and colonize neighboring domains. Euthanasia, now known as ‘mercy-killings,’ for example, is accepted in some contexts. This approach to human ontology is not only reductive and simplistic, but it is amoral and unethical. So being alert to a potential epistemological evolutionary trajectory that steers the ontological discourses engaged in this existential ‘path-building’ process is not impractical. Foresight thus has an ethical dimension.

I would like to mention only two illustrations of ‘feedback’. ‘Sentient feedback’ is exhibited in a system when ‘its behaviour is governed in part by changes in variables that can withstand wide fluctuation without system impairment, but which would be followed by states detrimental to the system if corrective activity were not quickly forthcoming.’[23] Foresight anticipates the corrective activity. It may even eliminate its need outright.  

This is the first ‘type’ of feedback that fits our purpose. This type of feedback responds to stimuli after their occurrence. It takes place as an adjustment. This is how the dynamics of ‘ambiguity’ and ‘uncertainty’ occur in a scenario of the logic of emergency (e.g. responses to 9-11, or even meteorological catastrophes and climate change). The deficiencies in the system are corrected through ‘sentient feedback’ that corrected policy errors to ensure the system was not impaired. The preservation of the ideal system is the primary objective of all initiatives. Sometimes goals are redefined. Yet one notes little radical change. Often, evolutionary change is slow and cumbersome.

Another form of feedback serves to pre-empt deficiencies in systems by responding to threatening states before they occur by basing judgments on antecedents. These may be referred to as ‘anticipatory feedback’. [24], Protecting the system from impairment is one of the primary goals of these methodologies. Doctrines of preemption or deterrence, or even risk management or incapacitation, related to, for example, terrorism are reliant on these principals. A concrete prototypical system directing international trade could be the IMF-WTO et al cluster. Such a system would be structured by its own restricted language. The strict adherence to the pre-established criteria would stifle creativity and innovation. Potential foresight would be transformed to goal-directed despotic sanctions. Foresight transcends this mechanistic approach.

The concepts born of, restricted by, dependent on, or attached to, ‘cybernetic-reasoning’ - and so ‘feedback’- are to our knowledge the cause of a latent epistemological obstacle, restriction, or contradiction. This sort of deductive or empirical method can receive erroneous interpretations. Moreover, aggregating atomised indicators does not give an accurate account of each individual component along its trajectory, nor does it take into account such liabilities as ‘digressions’ or the spatio-temporal reality beyond or outside the controlled area and its predetermined optimal status.

This system groups together aggregates bound by the definition of its goal; but it ignores any concept of ‘ontological primacy’. As the flows are led in predetermined patterns we rest our analysis on reading the flow charts born from ‘feedback’. Intermediary interruptions are not always taken into account. Reading F.H. George’s ‘Philosophical Foundations of Cybernetics’ one immediately notes that this theory is far too flexible in jettisoning criticism. 

This ‘method’ may reduce essentialism or metaphysics, but to a certain extent it is mechanistic and deterministic. It may serve social-psychology to examine and predict consumption profiles, for example, but it does not necessarily explain the existence of these consumers. There can be no ontology based on this schema. It can be used to gauge or profile subjects or objects being dominated; it cannot be used to liberate or emancipate them. Its temporalizations are not ‘supra-dimensionalised’, ‘a-dimensionalised’, or ‘a-temporalised’. This is why ‘foresight’ is so important. It liberates language from morphological, grammatical and syntactical enclosures, (that are also conceptual boundaries), to probe and generate untested possibilities. Foresight transcends both diachronic and synchronic approaches by radically deploying innovative conceptual tools not bound or defined by rationality templates.

Broadly speaking, cybernetic-reasoning consists of piecemeal temporalizations that are laboriously assembled. It can be useful to interact with environmental stimuli, but it cannot operate outside its predetermined ‘rationality-template’, not matter how complex and versatile the ‘template’ may appear in any set of possible permutations. Two computers using Artificial Intelligence and cybernetic reasoning could play master-class chess. Winning would simply be a matter of mathematical value. They would not experience any anxiety, stress, excitement, or pleasure. The opposing player (a computer) would be classified according to former ‘pattern-formations’. Neither system could distract the other or use any form of psychological deliberation. All games would be [pre] determined. This exemplifies the difference between ‘forecast’ and ‘foresight’ and excludes the possibility of assuming they are ‘incongruent counterparts’.  

The cybernetic-reasoning schema of feedback (and ‘forecast’) is a form of ‘classified thinking’. Bachelard states that ‘concepts are drawers in which knowledge may be classified; they are also ready-made garments which do away with the individuality of knowledge that has been experienced. The concept soon becomes lifeless thinking, by definition, it is a classified thinking’.[25] Can we transcend these neat positivist schemas, this lifeless thinking, this classified thinking? Foresight seeks to address this dilemma.

Bachelard is critical of ‘correspondences that have been examined too empirically’.[26] He speaks of a ‘need to ‘dephilosophize’ to shun the allures of culture to place ourselves on the margin of convictions acquired through long philosophical inquiry on the subject of scientific thinking. Philosophy makes us ripen quickly, and crystallises us in a state of maturity’.[27]  Foresight partially resolves this creativity seizure. Wild card management systems, for example, attempt to exit from this classified thinking.

CONCLUSION

Restricted resources are often subject to regulatory controls that attempt to secure smooth exchange transitions. Commodities that are exposed to volatile environmental conditions either in production or distribution are protected by networked underwriting and secure reserve provisions. These mechanisms are so swift and efficient in securing contingency, that one can accurately forecast allowances for indemnity. Futures markets, re-insurance, and even some aspects of stock markets are indicative of this reliability. The fact that we can even talk of indemnity, demurrage, insurance, or contingency illustrate our appraisals confirm a degree of subjectivity, unpredictability and inexplicability that we cater for. Meteorology is perhaps one area of recent interest testing; terrorism another. All very impressive.

Discussing the volatility of dependency on fossil fuels both for consumers as well as for producers, former Saudi oil minister and OPEC delegate, Shiek Yamani, succinctly stated that people did not leave the ‘Stone Age’ because of a lack of stones. In spite of deceivingly accelerated technological change, our dependency on fossil fuels epitomizes the fact that we seem unable to address this creativity seizure or exit from this impasse. Foresight can assist innovation management address these problems.

Forcing human behaviour descriptions or observations to fit neat schema and dismissing misfits as pathologies has proved to be costly and unethical. Attempting to forcefully direct the future according to predetermined goals has wrecked havoc and depleted strategic resources. Maintaining complex structural infrastructure has not settled disparities or justice. Reconciling consumption with production, experience with theory, or the past with the future, cannot be met without the analytic discernment of reality. Uncertainty and ambiguity are recurring features of this reality. In the past such discrepancies were addressed by the deployment of historicism, myths, irrational values, faith and belief systems, all to a certain extent still prevalent today. Some contexts have re-structured their plausibility structures or value-definitions to facilitate uncertainty and ambiguity.

Foresight can be developed to steer the future more coherently. Research and development of foresight need hybrid approaches that engage participants willing and able to transgress, explore, and innovate creatively. New knowledge clusters need to be designed and assembled to tri-dimensionalise time to look at the future free from the misconceptions of the past.








References


[1] Wagner, 1995, A Sociology of Modernity, London, Routledge, p 147
[2] Wagner, 1995,A Sociology of Modernity, London, Routledge,  p 148
[3] Foucault, 2003, The Order of Things, London, Routledge, p.80
[4] Foucault, 2003: The Order of Things, London, Routledge p.83
[5] Foucault, 2002: The Archaeology of Knowledge, London Routledge, p74
[6] Canguilhem, 1989, Problemes et Controverses, Paris, Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, p.14
[7] Foucault, 2003: The Order of Things, London, Routledge p.268
[8] Popper, 1989, Conjectures and Refutations, The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, London: Routledge, p. 34
[9] Russell, 1994, Logic and Knowledge, London: Routledge, p270
[10] Benn, 1997, Adults Count Too, London, NIACE, p 29
[11] Russell, 1994: Logic and Knowledge, London: Routledge 146
[12] Wittgenstein, 1997, Tractatus Logicus Philosophicus, London Routledge, p.65
[13] Adorno, 1982, Against Epistemology, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, p.22
[14] Adorno, 1982: Against Epistemology, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, p 11
[15] Bachelard, 1971, The Poetics of Reverie, Boston, Beacon Press, p. 4
[16] Gadamer, 1976, Philosophical Hermeneutics, Berkeley, University o California Press, p/ xxvi
[17] Gadamer, 1976: Philosophical Hermeneutics, Berkeley, University o California Press, p/ 39
[18] Gadamer, 1976 Philosophical Hermeneutics, Berkeley, University o California Press, p/:11
[19] Audi,1999, The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge, CUP, p. 173-4
[20] Sayre, 1976, Cybenetics and The Philosophy of Mind, London, Routledge, p.28
[21] Sayre, 1976, Cybenetics and The Philosophy of Mind, London, Routledge, p 39
[22] Sayre, 1976, Cybenetics and The Philosophy of Mind, London, Routledge, p 54
[23] Sayre, 1976, Cybenetics and The Philosophy of Mind, London, Routledge, p 57
[24] Sayre, 1976, Cybenetics and The Philosophy of Mind, London, Routledge, p 58
[25] Bachelard, 1968, The Poetics of Space, NY, Orion Press, p.75
[26] Bachelard, 1968 The Poetics of Space, NY, Orion Press, p. 193
[27] Bachelard, 1968 The Poetics of Space, NY, Orion Press, p.236















[1] Wagner, 1995, A Sociology of Modernity, London, Routledge, p 147
[1] Wagner, 1995,A Sociology of Modernity, London, Routledge,  p 148
[1] Foucault, 2003, The Order of Things, London, Routledge, p.80
[1] Foucault, 2003: The Order of Things, London, Routledge p.83
[1] Foucault, 2002: The Archaeology of Knowledge, London Routledge, p74
[1] Canguilhem, 1989, Problemes et Controverses, Paris, Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, p.14
[1] Foucault, 2003: The Order of Things, London, Routledge p.268
[1] Popper, 1989, Conjectures and Refutations, The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, London: Routledge, p. 34
[1] Russell, 1994, Logic and Knowledge, London: Routledge, p270
[1] Benn, 1997, Adults Count Too, London, NIACE, p 29
[1] Russell, 1994: Logic and Knowledge, London: Routledge 146
[1] Wittgenstein, 1997, Tractatus Logicus Philosophicus, London Routledge, p.65
[1] Adorno, 1982, Against Epistemology, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, p.22
[1] Adorno, 1982: Against Epistemology, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, p 11
[1] Bachelard, 1971, The Poetics of Reverie, Boston, Beacon Press, p. 4
[1] Gadamer, 1976, Philosophical Hermeneutics, Berkeley, University o California Press, p/ xxvi
[1] Gadamer, 1976: Philosophical Hermeneutics, Berkeley, University o California Press, p/ 39
[1] Gadamer, 1976 Philosophical Hermeneutics, Berkeley, University o California Press, p/:11
[1] Audi,1999, The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge, CUP, p. 173-4
[1] Sayre, 1976, Cybenetics and The Philosophy of Mind, London, Routledge, p.28
[1] Sayre, 1976, Cybenetics and The Philosophy of Mind, London, Routledge, p 39
[1] Sayre, 1976, Cybenetics and The Philosophy of Mind, London, Routledge, p 54
[1] Sayre, 1976, Cybenetics and The Philosophy of Mind, London, Routledge, p 57
[1] Sayre, 1976, Cybenetics and The Philosophy of Mind, London, Routledge, p 58
[1] Bachelard, 1968, The Poetics of Space, NY, Orion Press, p.75
[1] Bachelard, 1968 The Poetics of Space, NY, Orion Press, p. 193
[1] Bachelard, 1968 The Poetics of Space, NY, Orion Press, p.236

[1]

No comments:

Post a Comment